It is one of the quirks of the
history of philosophy that philosophical reflection has tended to get dragged
along behind the sciences. Somehow, philosophy (or rather, philosophers) has
been so entranced by the development of a particular science that they have believed
that their own thinking or perhaps, the thinking of humanity in general, should
proceed along similar lines.
The phenomenon is not new of
course. Descartes was a mathematician as well as a philosopher and thought
that philosophy should proceed mathematically. Famously (or perhaps infamously)
Spinoza thought that ethics could be done geometrically. He was not, of course,
daft enough to suppose that you could draw ethical diagrams and work out
angles, but axioms and inferences are to be found in his work. Locke understood
what he was doing as clearing away the undergrowth for natural philosophy – Newtonian
science in his case – to prevail. Hume thought that he could reduce morals to a
science, and so on down the line. The reputation of science for being a
paradigm of human thought and clarity has a long history.
Other subjects have followed
suit, of course. We have historical sciences, economic sciences, social
sciences and so on, all trying possibly to accrue some of the impacts that the
sciences, usually understood as the physical sciences, have on the world.
People have said to me of their social science projects when I have shown them
how to obtain a full set of data “That is more scientific”. I am still trying
to work out what that means, but then I am not a social scientist.
Theology, of course, is not immune
to this movement. Recently there has been a spate of concepts flying around to
use some of the approaches of science to a method in theology – a scientific
theology. This stuff is interesting, but it is a little difficult to see
exactly how it helps. Theology, thinking about God, is not science, where
science is thinking about things in the world.
It is possible that there is a
link between the doing of science and the doing of other subjects. The people
who consider that science is a paradigm of human thought have something of a
point but not, perhaps, in quite the way they might have expected. The link is,
of course, the human mind and brain. I do not want to get into the debate as to
the difference or identity of the human brain and the human mind, but just to
say that whatever it is, the same thing does the thinking behind science,
history, theology and everything else. If (and it might be a sizeable if) the
physical sciences give a paradigm of how we think, then we might be able to
think a bit more clearly about other subjects.
To be fair to the philosophers I
have mentioned above, and to everyone else who has trodden his path, I doubt if
anyone was naïve enough to believe that the problems of philosophy could be
solved by applying particular scientific or mathematical methods. It was the
regularity, the testing, the clarity of thought and derivation that they were
all after. We cannot clear away the undergrowth of thought without clarifying
our understandings, our concepts and our knowledge of how we came to be here,
in our current intellectual climate. Physical science, it is thought, does away
with the fuzziness.
Unfortunately, my experience of
doing physics is that in a research context at least, fuzziness is the norm. True,
we attempt to work our way through things, to chop up the bits we do not
understand into bits that we do and then reassemble them, but if things were
easy or clear, there would be a lot less research around. Isaac Asimov once
said the most powerful words in science are not ‘Eureka!’ but ‘That’s funny’,
and he has a point. Scientists at least should be confident to say ‘I don’t
know’, but that is often not how science and its progress are viewed.
The acclaim which scientific
advances have accrued over the centuries have affected the self-confidence of
other subjects. True, by comparison with mathematics and physics, the social
sciences are new kids on the block, but, on the whole, most subjects are either
cowed by scientific method or claim to use it for themselves. Interestingly, as
a physicist, I do not remember ever having a lecture on ‘The Scientific Method’.
The nearest I recall was a principle investigator calling a slightly naïve research
student a clot for changing two variables in an experiment at a time and thus
not being able to say which had caused the difference in the result. In other
subjects it seems, research methods are widely taught.
The upshot of this accumulation
of glamour to the physical sciences is that other subjects either retreat into
themselves, arguing more and more over finer and finer points of nuance, or
they subjugate themselves entirely to (mis-)understandings of science and what
it can achieve. This is true of some trends in theology, where misreadings of
relativity and (more often) quantum mechanics can lead to some very strange views
about spirituality and truth claims. Fortunately, the mainstream of the subject
has largely recovered from such weirdness, but they still happen (and, even
more oddly, get published).
The physical sciences, however,
are not quite as arrogant or all-conquering as views of them (or views put
forward by some scientists) would have us believe. They may well be paradigms
of how humans can think, intentionally, about a particular subject or problem.
By this I mean that a lot of the things we do in science relate to problem-solving, from the simple (‘Where is the leak in my vacuum system?') to the more
complex (‘How do I integrate this equation?’) and beyond; the most famous in
modern physics would be Einstein’s wondering what it would be like to sit on a
photon. But, as I have tried to suggest, this is not the whole arena of human
thinking. We do not spend our entire time problem solving, even as working
scientists. There is a lot more to life than science.
No comments:
Post a Comment