According to some, modern science
has conquered the world. Some scientists, and some others, have been so
impressed by the achievements of science that they believe that everything is a
scientific problem and that all scientific problems can be solved. It is just
a matter of time, effort and the application of the scientific method.
Other problems that people have,
such as decisions over life and death, whether to fall in love (insofar as that
might be a decision), how to bring up children, whether to read this novel or
watch that television program can all, under this model, be solved by
scientific means. A quick brain scan to establish which areas light up with
activity when you think about your proto-beloved and you can get the go-ahead
for a relationship. The reason we do not do this is that the technology is not
quite there yet, and it might take a while to obtain relevant results.
That does not stop some people,
of course, from arguing that more or less everything is subject to scientific
control and experiment. Nothing else exists – our thoughts about our beloved
are ‘nothing but’ brain activity. How we get for a bunch of jumping neurons to
a conscious thought about our beloved (or whatever else, of course) is never
really explained. Science is reductionist, on the whole, so we can drill down
from thoughts to neurons hopping, but not the other way terribly successfully.
The ultimate in this sort of
thinking was perhaps the philosophical movement known as Logical Positivism. For
various reasons the proponents of this set of ideas (it was not really a
single, coherent, movement) was that everything had to verifiable or it could
be ruled out as legitimate discourse. The English version of this was promulgated
by A. J. Ayer in Language, Truth and Logic, first published in the 1930s. The
work introduced the idea of the verification principle, that a proposition is
said to be verifiable in the strong sense if and only if its truth could be
conclusively established in experience. In the weak sense, a proposition is
verifiable if experience could render it probable. This was tremendously
influential in Anglo-American philosophy.
The problem is that the
verification principle rules out a lot of our normal experience and
understandings. ‘Murder is wrong’ is not probable nor can it be verified by
experiment – you cannot go an murder a sample of people and establish that it
was wrong to do so in each and every case. The world simply does not work the
way this philosophy would like it to. Logical Positivists had to resort to
ideas such as emotionalism, arguing that a statement such as ‘Murder is wrong’
cannot be verified (a relief to those of us who would rather not see
philosophers on the street murdering people) but is an emotional response
instead. Our moral world is reduced to our emotional reactions: ‘Murder is
wrong’ is at the same level as ‘I love Bach’. Surely something has gone wrong
here.
There are other problems as well,
of course. Intentionally, Logical Positivists had a tendency to rule that
religious statements were non-sense assertions and then, by linguistic sleight
of hand aver that religion was nonsense. Now, of course, some religious
statements are nonsense, but no more than statements made in other walks of
life such as politics or science. The removal of metaphysics, religion and
morality from the realm of sense suggests that the whole agenda is a bit
flawed.
The verification principle, in
its bald form, is ‘no statement is true unless it is a tautology, evident from
the senses or self-evident’. Thus, ‘here is a tree’ is verifiably true, as is ‘all
unmarried men are bachelors’. As we have seen, ‘murder is wrong’ is not
verifiable, but then nor is ‘I love you’ ‘I will meet you tomorrow at five o’clock’
or ‘God sustains the world’. None of these latter statements would usually be
regarded as nonsense, however – they are intelligible, even if we cannot agree
with them.
The problem is with the
verification principle itself. In fact, the principle is self-stultifying.
Itself it is neither a tautology, self-evident not evident from the senses.
According to its own lights, then, the verification principle is nonsense, or
at least, non-sense. I doubt that there are many philosophers in the world who
would subscribe to it anymore, and few in the last fifty years or so who would
take is terribly serious, except as an example of how philosophy can go badly
wrong.
The influence of logical
positivism is, however, still widespread in the education system and among some
rather, perhaps, philosophically naïve scientists. To be fair, it takes a while
for such problems to work their way out of a system. If the current crop of
teachers were trained by people who had been trained by those who subscribed to
logical positivism, perhaps we should not be surprised that it has a rather
long half-life. Similarly, most scientists are philosophically naïve. While
there might be late-night undergraduate discussions about the meaning of
quantum mechanics, science is simply not taught with an idea of the
philosophical background to it.
We therefore land up with eminent
scientists making pronouncements that would not be out of place on a logical
positivist’s platform. Among these might be ideas that the existence of God or
the usefulness of prayer should be subject to experiment. One of two of these
ideas have been tried out, of course, such as having people in hospital prayed
for and seeing if they recover more quickly than others, or praying that God
would strike the subject with lightening to prove He exists. This is all rather naïve (not to say silly)
but can be taken rather seriously by those who subscribe to a logical
positivist or total empiricist position.
The real failure in such thought
systems is not of science, or of theology or philosophy, but of individuals
failing to note that all positions actually return to metaphysics, some set of
underlying beliefs that cannot be justified, verified or claimed as being
universally true in all times and places. We stand on thousands of years of the
evolution of human thought, and we do not arrive at the ‘big questions’ without
some background knowledge and understanding. If we start to assume that the
place where we stand the only coherent one, then we have not just lost any
argument with those who differ from us, we have rather lost our ability to be
in the discussion at all.
No comments:
Post a Comment