Pontius Pilate’s question ‘What
is truth?’ addressed to Jesus, of course, invokes an irony to readers of the
Gospel of St John. A few chapters earlier, Jesus had told his disciples ‘I am
the way, and the truth, and the light’ (John 14:6). At his trial, Pilate
inquires of Jesus, the prisoner, ‘What is truth?’ The seeker asks the Truth the
nature of truth.
Without getting into the
complexities of how the truth could be embodied in a person, we can describe
the truth in two general theoretical ways. The first is the correspondence
theory and the second is coherence theory. The correspondence theory suggests
that truth is not mind-dependent in any significant way. If I see a field, a
field is before me. True propositions (‘I see a field’) correspond with reality
(there is a field which I am looking at). There are, of course, many nuances of
this theory which philosophers and others have delighted in engaging with, but
for the moment we can say that the correspondence theory is a form of realism:
what you see is what is there.
The coherence theory suggests
that what is true coheres with other propositions. A true proposition is in
agreement with many other justified true propositions. Those propositions, of course,
are coherent themselves with other justified true propositions, and so on. The
problem here is that all the coherent propositions might be wrong; the mental
structure could be entirely coherent within itself but bear no relationship to
the world.
Which of the theories is right?
Well, it depends on what you mean but I suspect that, practically, both have
elements of correctness in them. We do perceive and all of us believe that most
of our perceptions are correct. I can perceive my cat and stroke her. I see
her, feel her fur, hear her purring and so on, and these perceptions go
together to make the proposition ‘this is my cat’ which I accept as true. I do
not, unless I am writing like this, actually think like that. I recognise my
cat (and she recognises me) and we interact. There is some correspondence of
perception with the world; there is some coherence of perception with other
justified truths. We do not really seem to have advanced very far.
Ideas of truth rapidly run into
other, equally contested, ideas. Justification is one of them, as is belief.
One idea of knowledge is that it is a justified true belief. That is, if I believe
something that is both justified and true then I know something. Unfortunately,
this idea was debunked by Gettier (Gettier, E. L. (1963) 'Is Justified True
Belief Knowledge?', Analysis, vol. 23, no. 6, pp 121-123.) who showed that
some, at least, justified true beliefs are not knowledge. Knowledge, then, is
another contested concept.
These questions become rather
more acute when we look at something that assumes knowledge, truth and
justification. For example, an experiment in physics is built on a whole pile
of other experiments, theoretical constructs and the relationship between the
two. It is often said that theory is experiment laden and experiment is theory-laden, and that is true. The implications of that are far more significant than
usually imagined, however.
Suppose I, as I used to, want to
carry out an experiment in the spectroscopy of a plasma. This is just a jargon-ridden way of saying I want to look at the light emitted when I put a current
through a low-pressure gas, helium in my case. The current causes the atoms to
ionise, and the ions collapse into a thin pencil in the centre of the tube. As
they have extra energy, the atoms and ions emit light at energies (frequencies)
which are known from non-plasma experiments and from theoretical calculations.
The shape and location of these spectral lines can be measured and this yields
information about how the ions and atoms are affected by being in a plasma.
The experiment, then, rests on a large
quantity of assumptions and beliefs. Atomic theory is one of them, which tells
me where the spectral lines should be and also goes towards explaining the
broadening and shift of them. But there are more theoretical and experimental
items in the pile supporting this experiment – ideas about electrical currents
and ionisation; about the detection systems; theories of how spectrometers work
(the equipment used to spread the light out in wavelength so we can see the
spectral lines); measurements of the calibration of the equipment; statistics
about the repeatability of the results and so on.
The point here is not the details
of the experiments I conducted (you have to be an enthusiast for that), but the
mound of previous experiment, theory and testimony about those theories and experiments
that there is. The testimony comes in the form of scientific articles that are
peer-reviewed and published; in textbooks; in lectures, seminars, over coffee
and by working with others in the same laboratory, learning how stuff is done.
When the pile of stuff needed to understand a single experiment is considered,
it starts to seem a bit remarkable that we can achieve anything like knowledge.
No wonder that the claims of science often seem to be very cautious and modest.
They have to be.
Truth, in a scientific context,
is elusive. I cannot tell you what is true about an atom in a plasma. I can
tell you something about how the light from that atom (and a large number of
its colleagues) might be like, and what that may tell us about how the atoms
are behaving in those conditions. I have a model, partly mathematical, partly
in my head, of how these things work. But it is a model, it is not a
description of how these things work. Often we forget that our scientific
models are models, not descriptions of reality. Is a scientific (or any other
sort of) model ‘right’?
The best a scientific model can
do, really, is to predict some stuff (say the light emitted by a plasma) and we
can see whether the prediction and what we measure match. Further, we can try
to explain why they might not. I once received a note on an undergraduate
laboratory experiment report praising me for my ability to ‘explain (away) the
results’. As the foregoing suggests, I am still trying to work through the
implications of that.
No comments:
Post a Comment