The English philosopher John Locke is well known for arguing that we have no innate ideas. That is, we are not born with any ideas of our own, we develop them as we develop. This yields a problem for morality, in that society needs a population with a moral outlook and behaviour, but there is no innate understanding of what that might be.
Locke, thus, needs morality, in
the form of laws and ideas about duty and good, to come from somewhere. For him,
that somewhere is God. Duty cannot be understood without a law, and a law must
have a lawgiver. Since the human race is not born with laws, the lawgiver must
be outside the human race and must, therefore be God (Locke, 2014 [1690], pp. I, 3, 12).
This of course leads to another
problem, in that to ground morality we need to prove the existence of God. This
was not too much of a difficulty to Locke, given the society he was living in,
but is more of a problem for us. According to Locke we are intelligent
dependent beings under the direction of God. We cannot be independent because
then we would have no law.
There is a gulf here between
Locke and more recent ideas of morality. Recent accounts of humans argue that
we are independent individuals, and our moral standards are those which we have
chosen. Locke would argue that such a project, to choose our morality and live
by it, is doomed from the start. We are politically autonomous, in that we
cannot be governed without our consent, but not morally autonomous, and nor
would it be desirable for us to believe we were (Locke, 2006, p. 45).
Atheism, therefore, is a problem
for Locke, but is, of course, rife in society today. According to Locke there
cannot be any grounds for morality as a consequence of this. We simply act as
we see fit, having chosen our moral rules. If we look around the world today,
we can perhaps see the consequences of this in, perhaps, senior politicians
imposing rules on the population while ignoring them themselves. This makes
perfect sense if you have chosen a morality that exempts you from obeying rules
and if you are in a position not to be caught breaking the ones you have
imposed on other.
The problem is that this approach
can say nothing about anything being actually right or wrong. An action only
fits or does not fit with my chosen set of moral rules, and given that they are
my set of rules, I can change them as I wish. The fact that others are
forced to obey some rules other than their own is due to the coercive power of
the state. If I am in a position to avoid detection and punishment by the state
then I can ignore the rules which others cannot.
The philosophical problem here is
the objectivity of morality. By this we mean that if behaving in a certain way
is right, then that way must be findable by everyone. That is morality, being
good, goodness itself must be ‘out there’. Otherwise, our morality is just
that, ours, and it is ‘in here’ that is, a matter of my choice as to what I
think is right or good to do.
Philosophers have a hard time
proving anything is objective. Everything passes though our minds before we perceive
it, and so there is no good reason to believe that anything exists. This is the
sort of problem that gets philosophy a bad name, admittedly, but it does throw
up a problem which is usually ignored in everyday life. I walk around the
furniture because it is there, but my perception of the chair is not that
simple.
If we have a problem with
material objects in the world, we are clearly going to have an even worse
problem with non-material objects. So, things like God and morality, being, by
definition, not things in the world, are going to have a hard time being proved
to exist. I cannot prove the chair I am sitting on exists or continues to exist
if I leave the room. How on earth am I to prove that the good exists?
Critical realism can come to our
help here, at least partially. We do not have reasons to doubt the existence of
the chair, or its continued existence when I am not in the room. There might be
some unusual circumstances which might cause the chair to no longer exist when
I return, but these would be exactly that – unusual circumstances. Perhaps the
chair was destroyed because I left it too close to the fire. There are
explanations as to why the chair might not be there, but they suggest unusual occurrences.
Many people would say that
morality exists and that they follow it, at least most of the time. Most people
would claim that they seek the good for everyone, at least most of the time,
while admitting that often there are conflicting claims about what the good is,
exactly. That does not make morality objective, admittedly, but it might at
least suggest that morality and the good are available to most people if they
seek it. We live among real people in real situations, making real decision
about what is right or best to do.
The problem is, as Irish Murdoch
seems to have noted, is that to make decisions about what to do for the good,
we must see things clearly. By things I mean other people as well as objects in
the world and (in these days of climate crisis) the world in its fullness. We
have to navigate the world by seeing clearly, even if we see the world through
pictures or metaphors. Otherwise, we live in a fantasy world of our own
creation, in which case we can choose our morality to suit us and ignore the
reality of other people and their lives.
References
Locke, J. (2006). An Essay
Concerning Toleration and Other Writings on Law and Politics 1667-1683.
Oxford: OUP.
Locke, J. (2014 [1690]). Essay Concerning Human Understanding.
Ware: Wordsworth.